lynx   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

This category needs an editor. We encourage you to help if you are qualified.
Volunteer, or read more about what this involves.
Related

Contents
3024 found
Order:
1 — 50 / 3024
Material to categorize
  1. Rational Slack and Doxastic Grain.Bradford Saad - 2025 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 106 (3):173-185.
    This paper argues for granular permissivism, roughly the view that evidence is sometimes permissive between doxastic attitudes at different levels of grain. The argument identifies three sources of rational slack between granularly differing doxastic states: doxastic tidiness, safety, and evidential responsiveness. After arguing for granular permissivism and contrasting it with a more familiar, Jamesian form of permissivism, I show how granular permissivism offers an escape from some arguments against permissivism. I conclude by drawing out implications from granular permissivism for questions (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. From Epistemic States to Duties Not to Inquire?Leonardo Flamini - 2025 - Philosophia (2).
    Some philosophers consider knowledge the fundamental state whose presence or absence helps us decide when an inquiry is not permissible. Falbo has recently provided an alternative perspective in which epistemic improvement is what determines when an inquiry into a given question is not permitted: If it’s rational to be sure at t that, by inquiring, one won’t improve epistemically upon the question Q, then inquiry into Q is not permissible at t. In this paper, I will show that Falbo’s view (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. The New Evil Demon Problem and the Nature of Evidence.Thomas Kelly - 2025 - In Juan Comesaña & Matthew McGrath, Knowledge and rationality: essays in honor of Stewart Cohen. Abingdon, Oxon: Routledge. pp. 18-42.
    This chapter explores the challenge that the New Evil Demon Problem poses for so-called “externalist” theories of evidence. It argues that the best view of evidence is a liberalized form of externalism. According to that view, paradigmatic evidence in the sciences and elsewhere includes publicly known facts about the external world, evidence that we would not have in a hypothetical scenario in which we are the victims of radical deception. On the other hand, our evidence is not limited to our (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Implicit self-knowledge.Kristina Musholt - 2023 - In J. Robert Thompson, The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy and Implicit Cognition. New York, NY: Routledge.
    This chapter aims to give an overview of different types of knowledge that can reasonably be considered forms of implicit self-knowledge in contrast to explicit self-knowledge. It begins by clarifying the notion of self-knowledge, focusing on its epistemic feature of immunity to error through misidentification. It then considers theories of nonconceptual self-consciousness before discussing the relation between implicit and explicit forms of representation and (self-)knowledge. It suggests that nonconceptual, implicit self-knowledge might be understood in terms of knowledge-how and discusses the (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. The Methodologically Flawed Discussion about Deep Disagreement.Guido Melchior - 2025 - Episteme 22 (2):455-471.
    Questions surrounding deep disagreement have gained significant attention in recent years. One of the central debates is metaphysical, focusing on the features that make a disagreement deep. Proposals for what makes disagreements deep include theories about hinge propositions and first epistemic principles. In this paper, I criticize this metaphysical discussion by arguing that it is methodologically flawed. Deep disagreement is a technical or semi-technical term, but the metaphysical discussion mistakenly treats it as a common-sense concept to be analyzed and captured (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6. Reason and Rationality.T. W. Hung (ed.) - 2013 - Berlin, Boston: De Gruyter.
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7. (1 other version)Inquiring and Making Sure.Eliran Haziza - 2023 - Philosophical Topics 51 (2):185-195.
    It can be rational to inquire into what you already know, as cases of double-checking suggest. But, I argue, this is compatible with a knowledge aim of inquiry. In general, it can be rational to pursue an aim you’ve already achieved, and inquiry is no different. In particular, I argue that to double-check what you already know is to make sure you have knowledge, and that is still to aim at knowledge.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  8. Should You Defer to Individual Experts?Devin Lane - 2025 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 111 (1):216-234.
    Should you defer to individual experts? That is, when a single expert—rather than a group of experts or a expert consensus—testifies that p, should you believe that p? In this paper, I argue that the answer to this question is, generally speaking, “no.” My argument is based on the notion of a complexity‐based defeater. Some questions are complex in a sense that makes inquirers less reliable at answering them. Expert testimony tends to be about such questions. Expert testimony thus tends (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9. AI, Judgment, and Nonconceptual Content: A Critique of Dreyfus in Light of Neuro-Symbolic AI.Jacob Rump - forthcoming - Phänomenologische Forschungen.
    This paper examines Hubert Dreyfus' phenomenological critique of AI in light of contemporary large language models (LLMs) and emerging hybrid neuro-symbolic systems. While Dreyfus championed connectionist approaches over rule-based AI (GOFAI), his nonconceptualist framework faces limitations when applied to modern hybrid systems that combine neural networks with symbolic reasoning. I argue that Dreyfus' failure to account for intentional content in absorbed coping creates problems for explaining how nonconceptual significance can constrain the conceptual—a crucial issue for evaluating hybrid AI systems that (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Rationality, Responding to Reasons, and the First Person.Keshav Singh - 2025 - Res Philosophica 102 (3):239-262.
    Despite many disagreements, contemporary theorists of rationality largely agree that substantive rationality is to be understood in terms of correctly responding to reasons. While recent literature focuses on questions about the relationship between substantive and structural rationality, or which kinds of normative reasons are involved in substantive rationality, comparatively little attention has been paid to the question of what it is to correctly respond to reasons. Recent dispositionalist accounts of correctly responding to reasons mark an exception to this trend. In (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. The PSR as a practical principle in Kantian ethics.Karl Schafer - 2024 - Belgrade Philosophical Annual 37 (3):73-90.
    The Principle of Sufficient Reason (PSR) is the canonical expression of the idea of reality as fundamentally rational or intelligible, such that there is always a sufficient ground or explanation for everything about which such questions can be asked. In this essay, I argue that recent attempts to rehabilitate the PSR, despite their many virtues, have not gone far enough in emphasizing the centrality of this principle within all areas of philosophy - both theoretical and practical. Thus, I hope to (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. On the rationality of thought-insertion judgments.Víctor M. Verdejo - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (5):2076-2099.
    Subjects experiencing thought insertion disown thoughts they are introspectively aware of. According to what I call “the rationality hypothesis”, thought-insertion reports are not merely intelligible, but also express, or potentially express, fully rational judgments in the light of highly disruptive experience. I argue that the hypothesis is ethically and theoretically motivated, and provides two insights into the philosophical significance of reports by subjects with schizophrenia. First, the reports can be seen as evidence that rational judgments of ownership of a thought (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13. Kantian Reason: The Capacity for Understanding Entails an Understanding of Intelligibility.Karl Schafer - forthcoming - Kant Yearbook.
    In what follows, I argue that, given a Kantian conception of reason as a capacity, possession of that capacity entails possession of an implicit understanding of what understanding or intelligibility itself is. In particular, I show that this follows from Kant’s conception of reason as the power or capacity for understanding or comprehension (Begreifen), together with several basic Kantian commitments about the nature of rational capacities. Through this argument, I hope to show that the core of the Kantian conception of (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Best Laid Plans: Idealization and the Rationality–Accuracy Bridge.Brett Topey - 2025 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 76 (2):477-494.
    Greaves and Wallace argue that conditionalization maximizes expected accuracy and so is a rational requirement, but their argument presupposes a particular picture of the bridge between rationality and accuracy: the best-plan-to-follow picture. And theorists such as Schoenfield and Steel argue that it is possible to motivate an alternative picture—the best-plan-to-make picture—that does not vindicate conditionalization. I show that these theorists are mistaken: it turns out that if an update procedure maximizes expected accuracy on the best-plan-to-follow picture, it is guaranteed to (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15. Rational Hypothesis.Michele Palmira - 2023 - Philosophical Topics 51 (2):197-219.
    There are scenarios in which letting one’s own views on the question whether p direct one’s inquiry into that question brings about individual and collective epistemic benefits. However, these scenarios are also such that one’s evidence doesn’t support believing one’s own views. So, how to vindicate the epistemic benefits of directing one’s inquiry in such an asymmetric way, without asking one to hold a seemingly irrational doxastic attitude? To answer this question, the paper understands asymmetric inquiry direction in terms of (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. On Instrumental Zetetic Normativity.Leonardo Flamini - 2023 - Philosophical Topics 51 (2):161-184.
    Jane Friedman claims that when we inquire, there is a tension between the instrumental normativity of our inquiries and some basic epistemic norms: The former forbids what the latter permit. Moreover, she argues that since the instrumental normativity of inquiry is epistemic, the previous tension shows that our current conception of epistemic normativity is incoherent and needs to be revised. To solve the problem, she suggests that all our epistemic norms should be considered “zetetic”, namely, norms of inquiry. In this (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. Norms of Inquiry.David Thorstad - 2023 - Philosophical Topics 51 (2):135-160.
    Epistemologists have recently proposed a number of norms governing rational inquiry. My aim in this paper is to unify and explain recently proposed norms of inquiry by developing a general account of the conditions under which inquiries are rational, analogous to theories such as evidentialism and reliabilism for rational belief. I begin with a reason-responsiveness conception of rationality as responding correctly to possessed normative reasons. I extend this account with a series of claims about the normative reasons for inquiry that (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18. Misleading Higher-Order Evidence and Rationality: We Can't Always Rationally Believe What We Have Evidence to Believe.Wade Munroe - 2025 - Episteme 22 (1):99-125.
    Evidentialism as an account of theoretical rationality is a popular and well-defended position. However, recently, it's been argued that misleading higher-order evidence (HOE) – that is, evidence about one's evidence or about one's cognitive functioning – poses a problem for evidentialism. Roughly, the problem is that, in certain cases of misleading HOE, it appears evidentialism entails that it is rational to adopt a belief in an akratic conjunction – a proposition of the form “p, but my evidence doesn't support p” (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. What is sufficient evidence?Clayton Littlejohn - 2026 - In Scott Stapleford, Kevin McCain & Matthias Steup, Evidentialism at 40: New Arguments, New Angles.
    How should we understand the notion of sufficient evidence? How should we deal with the worry that any attempt to use a threshold of support to characterise this notion would be arbitrary? In this paper, I argue that the most familiar way of understanding a threshold is unworkable but also argue that it would be misguided to do away with a threshold-centred account. I argue that we should approach sufficiency in the theoretical realm much in the way that we would (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Rational Inconsistency Against Non-skeptical Infallibilism.Nate Lauffer - 2025 - Acta Analytica 2025:1-16.
    Recent epistemological literature features compelling and novel arguments for thinking that an agent can rationally believe each member of a set of propositions while knowing that one of the members is false. Perhaps more provocatively, these proponents of "Rational Inconsistency," as it were, claim that it’s also possible to know each true member of the set while knowing that one of the members is false. Call this "Knowledgeable Inconsistency." In this article, I explain why, if Knowledgeable Inconsistency is true, then, (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. From Heuristic to Reflective Worldview: A Mathematical Model of Belief Dynamics.Oliver Marc Wittwer - manuscript
    NOTE: This is an early preprint version. The definitive, citable "Version of Record" of this paper has been archived on Zenodo and can be found under the DOI 10.5281/zenodo.15682919. Please use the Zenodo version exclusively for all citations. -/- This paper presents a mathematically formalized model for describing and analyzing worldview dynamics, distinguishing between heuristic and reflective worldviews. It formalizes the psychological mechanisms of authority-based belief and cognitive dissonance, demonstrating how humans evaluate new information through the filter of their existing (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22. Knowledge, blameworthiness, and being in a position to know.Guido Melchior - forthcoming - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy.
    S is usually assumed to be blameworthy for harmful actions only if S knew or should have known about the harmful consequences of her actions. Since there is usually assumed to be a connection between one’s obligations and one’s capacities, expressed by the slogan that ought implies can, one’s capacities to know have an impact on one’s blameworthiness. In this paper, I will investigate this relationship between blameworthiness and knowledge in reverse order. I will first investigate the meaning of (not) (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Withhold by default: a difference between epistemic and practical rationality.Chris Tucker - 2025 - Philosophical Studies 182 (3):817-840.
    It may seem that epistemic and practical rationality weigh reasons differently, because ties in practical rationality tend to generate permissions and ties in epistemic rationality tend to generate a requirement to withhold judgment. I argue that epistemic and practical rationality weigh reasons in the same way, but they have different "default biases". Practical rationality is biased toward every option being permissible whereas epistemic rationality is biased toward withholding judgment's being required.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  24. Depression, Intelligibility, and Non-Rational Causation.Quinn Hiroshi Gibson - 2025 - Neuroethics 18 (2):1-14.
    What I call “exogenous” depression differs from “endogenous” depression by being _intelligibly_ related to adverse conditions in the world. Because exogenous depression is caused in this way, any purely intrinsic characterization of it is incomplete. Endogenous depression, by contrast, does not resist intrinsic characterization. Further, in exogenous depression, what we are able to understand by empathetic imagination _goes together_ with well-established causes, so there is no tension between intelligibility and objectivity. This distinction can be drawn in a way which is (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Paulin J. Hountondji and the Defense of the Universal: An Interview with Carmen De Schryver (Part II). [REVIEW]Zeyad El Nabolsy & Carmen De Schryver - 2024 - Borderlines.
    Zeyad el Nabolsy: Hountondji, while critical of the ethnosciences, namely the study of things like “traditional” mathematical and astronomical knowledge from an anthropological perspective, does defend the importance of studying what he calls “endogenous knowledge”. Can you say something about this? -/- Carmen De Schryver: We should say something about his choice of the term “endogenous” over the term “indigenous”. He really wants to question the idea that, insofar as we are talking about African systems of knowledge, we are talking (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Robustness and the Distinctive Properties of Epistemic Ideals.Marc-Kevin Daoust - forthcoming - Australasian Journal of Philosophy.
    Why care about ideal epistemic norms? Why not merely care about norms that agents like us can actually meet? In this paper, I make two claims. First, I argue that, if we want robust epistemic norms, we can’t just do idealised epistemology. We need to confirm that the results and observations that are central in idealised epistemology also obtain in other contexts. Second, I argue that, if we really want to capture the fundamental nature of epistemic normativity, we need the (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Unfinished Business. Rational Attitudes in Reasoning.Julia Staffel - 2025 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Explaining how people reason is central to understanding ourselves as human beings. Complex deliberations that take unexpected turns are central to many good detective stories, but they are also ubiquitous in everyday life and academic research. While philosophers have studied both ends of complex deliberations – learning new information and reaching justified conclusions – little has been said about our states of mind when we’re in the middle of thought. Yet, this stage of intellectual limbo is where we often produce (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28. From deep disagreement to rationally irresolvable disagreement.Guido Melchior - 2024 - In Fabio Paglieri, The Cognitive Dimension of Social Argumentation. Proceedings of the 4th European Conference on Argumentation. pp. 97-110.
  29. Defending the Enkratic Requirement.Martin Grajner & Eva Schmidt - forthcoming - In Nick Hughes, Essays on Epistemic Dilemmas.
    One influential response to apparent higher-order dilemmas implies that agents can rationally both believe p on the basis of their evidence and simultaneously believe that their evidence does not support believing p. This possibility of rational epistemic akrasia seems to call into question the Enkratic Requirement, which prohibits believing a proposition p according to one’s lower-level evidence, while believing that one’s lower-level evidence does not support believing p. In this chapter, we explore two ways to defend the Enkratic Requirement. First, (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. “Belief” and Belief.Eric Marcus - 2025 - European Journal of Philosophy 33 (1):220-232.
    Our interest in understanding belief stems partly from our being creatures who think. However, the term ‘belief’ is used to refer to many states: from the fully conscious rational state that partly constitutes knowledge to the fanciful states of alarm clocks. Which of the many ‘belief’ states must a theory of belief be answerable to? This is the scope question. I begin my answer with a reply to a recent argument that belief is invariably weak, i.e., that the evidential standards (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. Germaine de Staël’s Theory of the Passions.Eveline Groot - 2024 - In Ruth Edith Hagengruber, Teaching women philosophers, Ideas and Concepts from Women Philosophers’ Writings Over 2000 Years. Cham: Springer. pp. 93-112.
    Germaine de Staël’s theory of the impassioned nature of human beings, as set out in her work De l’influence des passions sur le bonheur des individus et des nations (1796), provides an insightful account of a sentimentalist theory in which human sensibility and emotionality are understood to be a core part of moral thought. In this work, Staël develops a psychological anthropology and moral theory that presents an interplay between the rational and the sentimental as one of its core aspects. (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Misleading Higher-Order Evidence, Conflicting Ideals, and Defeasible Logic.Aleks Knoks - 2021 - Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 8.
    Thinking about misleading higher-order evidence naturally leads to a puzzle about epistemic rationality: If one’s total evidence can be radically misleading regarding itself, then two widely-accepted requirements of rationality come into conflict, suggesting that there are rational dilemmas. This paper focuses on an often misunderstood and underexplored response to this (and similar) puzzles, the so-called conflicting-ideals view. Drawing on work from defeasible logic, I propose understanding this view as a move away from the default meta-epistemological position according to which rationality (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Certainty’s Bulwark at Rationality’s Edge? Reframing the Disagreement between Humean Skeptics and Constitutivist Hinge Epistemologists.Kwing-Yui Wong - 2025 - Rivista Italiana di Filosofia del Linguaggio 18 (2):56-65.
    This paper critically examines Coliva and Palmira’s characterization of the disagreement between Humean skeptics and hinge epistemologists as a distinctive kind of conceptual disagreement. Humean skepticism requires evidential justification for all rational beliefs, presenting a narrower conception of rationality. This contrasts with constitutivist hinge epistemology, which posits that our unwarranted hinge propositions — the basic certainties which makes the justifications for ordinary empirical propositions possible — are constitutive of the concept of epistemic rationality, thus they are also rationally accepted by (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Contextualism and the truth norm.Darren Bradley - forthcoming - Episteme.
    What should we believe? One plausible view is that we should believe what is true. Another is that we should believe what is rational to believe. I will argue that both these theses can be accounted for once we add an independently motivated contextualism about normative terms. According to contextualism, the content of ‘ought’ depends on two parameters – a goal and a modal base (or set of possible worlds). It follows that there is a sense in which we should (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Review of: Knauff, M., & Spohn, W. (Eds.), 2021, The Handbook of Rationality, MIT Press.Sarah Sterz - 2025 - Erkenntnis 90 (2):771-776.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Suspension as a mood.Benoit Guilielmo & Artūrs Logins - forthcoming - Philosophical Psychology.
    Suspension of judgment is a ubiquitous phenomenon in our lives. It is also relevant for several debates in contemporary epistemology (e.g., evidentialism/pragmatism; peer-disagreement/higher-order evidence; inquiry). The goal of this paper is to arrive at a better understanding of what suspension of judgment is. We first question the popular assumption that we call the Triad view according to which there are three and only three (paradigmatic) doxastic attitudes, namely, belief, disbelief, and suspension of judgment. We elaborate a cumulative argument regarding crucial (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. Pascal's Wager as a Decision Under Ignorance.André Neiva - forthcoming - Erkenntnis.
    In this paper, I examine Pascal's Wager as a decision problem where the uncertainty is massive, that is, as a decision under ignorance. I first present several reasons to support this interpretation. Then, I argue that wagering for God is the optimal act in a broad range of cases, according to two well-known criteria for decision-making: the Minimax Regret rule and the Hurwicz criterion. Given a Pascalian standard matrix, I also show that a tie between wagering for God and wagering (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. A Corpus Study on the Normativity of Rationality.Kevin Reuter, Lucien Baumgartner & Michael Messerli - forthcoming - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy.
    In this paper, we address a key question that has been central to discussions on rationality: is the concept of rationality normative or merely descriptive? We present the findings of a corpus-linguistic study revealing that people commonly perceive the concept of rationality as normative.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39. Curiosity and zetetic style in ADHD.Asbjørn Steglich-Petersen & Somogy Varga - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):897-921.
    While research on Attention Deficit Hyperactivity Disorder (ADHD) has traditionally focused on cognitive and behavioral deficits, there is increasing interest in exploring possible resources associated with the disorder. In this paper, we argue that the attention-patterns associated with ADHD can be understood as expressing an alternative style of inquiry, or “zetetic” style, characterized mainly by a lower barrier for becoming curious and engaging in inquiry, and a weaker disposition to regulate curiosity in response to the cognitive and practical costs associated (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Blame-validation: Beyond rationality? Effect of causal link on the relationship between evaluation and causal judgment.Valentin Goulette & Fanny Verkampt - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):436-455.
    The Culpable Control Model assumes that causal judgments are irrational: a negative evaluative reaction to an agent would lead individuals to overestimate his causal contribution to a harm. However, the extent to which these judgments deviate from criteria of rationality remains unclear. The two present studies aimed at investigating conditions under which this effect occurs. Participants red a vignette in which the evaluative reaction was operationalized through the agent’s motives (blameworthy, laudable). We also varied the causal link between the agent’s (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Reciprocity.Andrej Poleev - 2025 - Enzymes 23.
    A Review of: Joel Z. Leibo et al. A theory of appropriateness with applications to generative artificial intelligence. (2024) (in Russian) .
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. The Challenge of Quantum Mechanics to the Rationality of Science: Philosophers of Science on Bohr.Marij van Strien - 2023 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 37 (4):219-241.
    Bohr’s work in quantum mechanics posed a challenge to philosophers of science, who struggled with the question of whether and to what degree his theories and methods could be considered rational. This paper focuses on Popper, Feyerabend, Lakatos and Kuhn, all of whom recognized some irrational, dogmatic, paradoxical or even inconsistent features in Bohr’s work. Popper, Feyerabend, and Lakatos expressed strong criticism of Bohr’s approach to quantum physics, while Kuhn argued that such criticism was unlikely to be fruitful: progress in (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. Epistemic Responsibility: an Agent’s Sensitivity Towards the World.Wai Lok Cheung - 2024 - Logos and Episteme 15 (4):389-403.
    Stewart Cohen’s epistemic responsibility conception of epistemic justification in illustrating the problem of the new evil demon is assessed through some virtue-theoretic attempts, notably by Timothy Williamson and Clayton Littlejohn, whose accounts provide a good departure point to differentiate epistemic blamelessness through epistemic excusability via exercise of epistemic competence with epistemic recklessness. Some failure of epistemic sensitivity is through epistemic recklessness, and its epistemic blameworthiness is understood thus. I shall, having set the stage of epistemic justification in relation to epistemic (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. La rationalité de la théologie : perspectives et articulations.De Baenst Benoît, Gagnon Philippe, Rodrigues Paulo & Valinho Gomes Pedro (eds.) - forthcoming - Paris: Parole et silence.
  45. Is it ever rational to hold inconsistent beliefs?Martin Smith - 2024 - Philosophical Studies 181 (12):3459-3475.
    In this paper I investigate whether there are any cases in which it is rational for a person to hold inconsistent beliefs and, if there are, just what implications this might have for the theory of epistemic justification. A number of issues will crop up along the way – including the relation between justification and rationality, the nature of defeat, the possibility of epistemic dilemmas, the importance of positive epistemic duties, and the distinction between transitional and terminal attitudes.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Permissivism About Religious Belief.Elizabeth Jackson - manuscript
    In this chapter, I argue that theistic belief is permissive belief. This is not a universal claim about persons or normative domains, but the claim that, for many common bodies of evidence, epistemic rationality is permissive about whether God exists. Marks of a permissive belief are rational disagreement over time, rational disagreement over persons, and powerful evidence on both sides. I argue that theistic belief fits all these criteria. I also show how considerations from divine hiddenness support permissivism about theism. (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. 纳尔齐斯的盲影 (一项关于集体想象的社会心理研究).Roberto Thomas Arruda - 2024 - São Paulo: Terra à Vista.
    这项工作将探讨集体想象及其与现实和真理的关系的基本问题。首先,我们应该在概念框架中面对这个主题,然后对可证明的行为现实进行相应的事实分析。 我们不仅会采用方法论,还会主要采用分析哲学的原则和主张,这些原则和主张必将在整个研究中得到揭示,并可以通过佩雷斯所描述的特征来识别 : -/- “Rabossi (1975) 认为,可以通过考虑某些家族相似性来识别分析哲学。他认为分析哲学具有以下家族特征:对科学知识持积极态度;对形而上学持谨慎态度;将哲学视为概念任务,将概念分析视为方法;语言与哲学之间关系密切;注重寻求哲学 问题的论证性答案;寻求概念的清晰度。” -/- 这些核心概念涉及文化、社会、宗教、科学、哲学、道德和政治,它们属于个体和集体存在。 -/- 在本文中,我们不会进行辩论或争论。我们的目的不是系统地方法化、批评或提出证据。 -/- 这项研究基于分析反思。我们将尽可能彻底和深入地进行推测,并表达我们思考的结果。尽管该主题具有多学科性,并且方法论开放,接受所有科学领域的贡献,但这项工作属于心理学和本体论,或者换句话说,社会和本体论心 理学。 指导这种思想的自由主义方法论包容并考虑到与哲学和心理学认识论接近一致的一切。这种方法论不寻求证据,而是寻求任何性质和大小的现有证据之间的相互关系,并推断出真实事物的连贯意义。 许多伟大的思想家从不寻求争论、理论化或系统化,而是通过思考、冥想和谦卑的意识来接近真理。他们将成为我们的榜样和参考。虽然我们无法找到真相,但 我们可以肯定这一点:在很多情况下,我们将接近真相,在任何时候,我们都将远离谎言和不真实。 本文的主要范围是观察人类的一些基本进化属性,如创造力、想象力和联想,如何在智慧迷雾的阴影下成为一种危险的疾病。 .
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Unification without pragmatism.Keshav Singh - 2024 - Philosophical Issues 34 (1):234-252.
    Both actions and beliefs are subject to normative evaluation as rational or irrational. As such, we might expect there to be some general, unified story about what makes them rational. However, orthodox approaches suggest that the rationality of action is determined by practical considerations, while the rationality of belief is determined by properly epistemic considerations. This apparent disunity leads some, like Rinard (2019), to reject orthodox theories of the rationality of belief in favor of pragmatism. In this paper, I argue (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Non‐ideal epistemic rationality.Nick Hughes - 2024 - Philosophical Issues 34 (1):72-95.
    I develop a broadly reliabilist theory of non‐ideal epistemic rationality and argue that if it is correct we should reject the recently popular idea that the standards of non‐ideal epistemic rationality are mere social conventions.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Six Roles for Inclination.Zach Barnett - 2024 - Mind 133 (532):972-1000.
    Initially, you judge that p. You then learn that most experts disagree. All things considered, you believe that the experts are probably right. Still, p continues to seem right to you, in some sense. You don’t yet see what, if anything, is wrong with your original reasoning. In such a case, we’ll say that you are ‘inclined’ toward p. This paper explores various roles that this state of inclination can play, both within epistemology and more broadly. Specifically, it will be (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 3024
Лучший частный хостинг